Wednesday, July 17, 2019

Nancy Scheper-Hughes and the Question of Ethical Fieldwork

In 1974, Nancy Scheper-Hughes trave direct to a village in agrestic Ireland which she subsequent nicknamed B eachybran (Scheper-Hughes 2000-128)). Her findings there led her to egress Saints, Scholars and Schizophrenics Mental Illness in artless Ireland in 1979, in which she attempted to cond ane the affable causes of Irelands surprisingly exalted rates of schizophrenia (Scheper-Hughes 2000128). Saints was met with a bounce of censure from both the anthropological fellowship and the villagers who had served as her informants.The lit crit eventu all(prenominal)y led to Scheper-Hughes being expelled indefinitely from the village in which she had get goinged (Scheper-Hughes 2000118) and raised serious questions around the honest motive of anthropological inquiry. In this essay I will argue that Nancy Scheper-Hughes fieldwork in Ireland was essentially un honourable on the grounds that she honour equally wronged her participants with her fictionalized reintroduction of them, and that she did non strain their sure bear. That being said, she was also pull to geomorphologic analytic thinking, which is distinctly lacking in twenty-first century anthropological inquiry.Nancy-Scheper Hughes has oft been criticized for chastely wronging her informants in a renewing of moods, including split of screen, deception and misrepresentation (Schrag 2009140). These attacks did non come until much ulterior, however, and the initial complaints against her work were centered around her conclusions, which were perceived to be based on faulty methodological analysis including drawing conclusions without sufficient data to pay them, and misreading her informants re displaceions to her book (Messenger 198214).The villagers themselves were upset that she had malformed them, remarking that she had violated local reckons of hospitality (Scheper-Hughes 198213), depicted nonhing besides the negative aspects of Irish homespun life (Scheper-Hughes 2000119 ) and formed their idiosyncratic identities into fictional characters in her efforts to conceal them (Scheper-Hughes 198213). though perhaps well-intentioned, Scheper-Hughes attempt to conceal the identities of her informants turn uped in forming them into fragmented, fictional characters, according to the villagers themselves (Scheper-Hughes 198213).In this the villagers ar averageified, as she hid real numberity by entombment it inside archetypal representations which led to a misrepresentation of her informants. It turns reality into a caricature, life history into question the validity of her portrayals and so the bum of her entire analysis. Moreover, it is un elegant to the informants themselves because it gives faith for speech communication spoken by real people to fictional characters.At best, Scheper-Hughes attempt to encourage the individual privacy of her informants backfired and warped their identities into something wild and grounded in the misrepresentat ion of reality therefore, criticism from the villagers regarding her scattering of their identities argon indeed warranted. Clearly, Scheper-Hughes wronged her informants by fragmenting their words and contri aloneions, and by giving source to false identities when it was actually due to real ones. integrity informant actually remarked that she just didnt give us credit (Scheper-Hughes 2000119).And yet de fire her efforts to conceal the identities of her informants by disguising them as fictional characters, they were still fitting to identify themselves and each other (Schrag 2009150). Since the base feather purpose of identity concealment is to take an informants secrets intact by hiding them from society members, the fact that the villagers in Ballybran were able to re-construct each others identities in her published work shows that she did non ripely protect confidential learning, and therefore did not put the interests of her participants first.The anthropologist has a moral duty to protect the secrets of her informants once issued, curiously when publishing them, no matter when and where the interrogation was carried out. As Schrag asserts, this is simply the best way to treat them as benignants and not repositories of knowledge (2009145). Scheper-Hughes absolvely attempted to do this by subjecting her informants to anonymity if she had not, the villagers would not prolong been angry active their fragmented identities and scattered words.It is dupe, however, that she failed in this attempt, as the villagers were still able to recognize the pieces of themselves in her ethnography (Scheper-Hughes 2000150). It is not of necessity unethical to publish corporation and individual secrets indeed without them smashing ethnographical work would not be possible, curiously when investigating such hypothetical pips as illegal activities as a result of oppression and geomorphological inequalities. However, it is important to draw and discl ose such secrets under invite ethical guidelines.Informed live with is and was at the time of Scheper-Hughes fieldwork an important aspect of ethical search. Scheper-Hughes was criticized by Irish anthropologists for not obtaining the adept and informed combine of her participants before take oning her seek, and this criticism is warranted (Callahan 3111979). It is clear from the villagers re accomplishments when she returned to Ballybran some years later that this is in fact true. Scheper-Hughes herself remarked that many felt up betrayed by her book, and that they initially had no approximation what she would publish (Scheper-Hughes 2000148).Schrag argues that part of informed concur should be to communicate honestly the investigate objectives of the ethnographer, which Scheper-Hughes did not do (2009138). If she had done this to the fullest extent possible, the villagers would not have been shocked and mischief by her conclusions. Proper informed respond should inc orporate an agreement between the investigator and their participants which makes clear that whatever is disclosed to the ethnographer is fair game for publication.That being said, obtaining such consent john be a read of contention in anthropology, since it means that not only does the participant have to consent to a full disclosure of their individual(prenominal) information, but the ethnographer has to also consent to the opening night that not all desired information will be procurable for analysis and publication. This consensual agreement essential be part of any ethical fieldwork, and it is clear that Scheper-Hughes did not adhere to it.Since informed consent was already an established convention when she conducted her researchas evidenced by Eileen Kanes criticism of her lack of it (Messenger198214)even a relativist critique in this subject area would be fully warranted and justified. It is true that obtaining proper informed consent from informants means that not a ll information will be available to the ethnographer however, this does not necessarily mean that good ethnographic work cannot be accomplished.If the terminus of the ethnographer is to locate structural violence and subsequent inequalitieswhich I will argue later that it should bethan these would in theory be apparent without needing to obtain or divulge personal secrets to a large degree. Moreover, truthful attempts could be made to not set off the identity of the informants who do confess familiar details without resorting to scattering and dismantling them. wholly identities could be unplowed secret by not publishing revealing facts about an individual which are not purely undeniable to the collection or presentation of data.Multivocality is certainly important, but if direct quotes, lick descriptions and background information are kept to a minimum it would serve the triple purpose of concealing identity without fictionalizing it therefore, the chastening of Scheper- Hughes to keep identities in tact term also preserving the integrity of information provided within the unrelentingest confidence serves as a lesson to all anthropologists as to the necessity of full and proper informed consent.Keeping multivocality to a necessary minimum would also allow the ethnographer to do a more objective structural analysis, which is distinctly lacking in postmodern ethnography. Though it is important to protect the privacy of the individual on their terms through informed consent, it is also important to conduct quality analyses of structural inequalities with the objective of promoting the green good.One thing that can be said about the work of Scheper-Hughes is that she was act to pin top doging the hearty causes of schizophrenia in rural Ireland, which ultimately pointed fingers not at the villagers themselves but at the economic and social hardships that prompted them to act out a certain meat of psychological violence on their children (Scheper- Hughes 2000123). Schrag criticizes Scheper-Hughes for committing what he calls inflicted insight that is, forcing the villagers to realize painful truths about themselves that they did not ask for or gestate (2009151).I argue that this is not necessarily a breach of morals, and dep annihilates largely on the time and place in which the research is being conducted. If the inflicted insight is coming from a psychiatrist and is being offered to an individual under the strictest codes of patient confidentiality, then to break that code would be a severe breach of morality. Schrag is right claim that inflicted insight in a psychiatric environment is only if different from that in a social context (2009153).The former deals strictly with an individual, whereas the last mentioned deals with truths about structural violence which are embedded within society at large and are not necessarily apparent from the inside. In such cases, I argue that it is the moral obligation of the ethnographe r to point out the causes of structural violence, and simply doing so could prompt achieve within the biotic community itself to correct inequalities or systematic oppression.No action can be interpreted against a problem unless the cause is clear and this is sometimes hard to realize when one is immersed within ones ingest cultural framework. The anthropologist, as a humanand therefore moral beinghas a duty to seek out social reproductions of violence and form opinions about them. One cannot be too relativistic in ones work, and if the anthropologist takes a jut on one side or other it has the potential to call others to action as well.This is one thing that Nancy Scheper-Hughes did well, as exemplified by the fact that when she returned to Ballybran years by and by her initial research was carried out, one villager admitted that the childly mothers had been more inclined to show partiality to their children since the publication of the book, almost as if to spite her conclu sions (Scheper-Hughes 2000136). Clearly some action had been taken to reverse what Scheper-Hughes had concluded was one of the primary causes for schizophrenia that of parental disinterest in their children (2000131).Whether or not her conclusions were correct, she made them in the spirit of the collective good, and they prompted some native change from the villagers themselves. This is more than any postmodern ethnography has managed to do, and therefore the final lesson that anthropologists can take away from the case of Nancy Scheper-Hughes is that an ethnography can be a right on tool for change however it must be researched and written in an ethical way, one which adequately addresses and takes a jib on structural violence.In conclusion, I have argued that Nancy Scheper-Hughes fieldwork in rural Ireland was essentially unethical because she portrayed her informants as fictionalized caricatures and did not seek their full informed consent, which morally wronged her particip ants. That being said, she did pursue an analysis of structural violence which prompted some small action in her host community aft(prenominal) her book was published, a noble end which anthropologists have lost sight of in the postmodern era.Though her fieldwork led to her eventual(prenominal) expulsion from Ballybran and continues to undergo scrutiny by the anthropological community, it is nevertheless an important case study in the necessity of strict ethical standards when working in the field. Its situation within a lost dogma of structuralism also makes it important for futurity anthropologists to examine as an example not of art for arts sake, but as a voice for the parking lot good.

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.